Posts

Coercing Virtue or Superintending Constitutional Order? A Comment on Munir Zulu and Celestine Mukandila v. Attorney General

In the article by Dr. O’Brien Kaaba, the role of the Zambian Constitutional Court in the constitutional amendment process is critically examined.
Views




By Dr. O’Brien Kaaba

July 14, 2025

 

What should be the role of the courts in a constitutional amendment process? Should courts have the power to block a constitutional amendment process?  Those are the questions the Constitutional Court had to grapple with in the case of Munir Zulu and Celestine Mukandila v. Attorney General 2025/CCZ/009. It was not the first time the Zambian judiciary was asked to intervene in the constitution amendment or constitution-making process. While the Courts have in all past similar cases declined the invitation, in the current case, the Court gladly took the opportunity to assert its role in the constitutional reform process.

The petitioners in this case challenged the constitutionality of the constitution-making process that was embarked on by the government, premised on announcements by the President and the Minister of Justice, as it lacked a wide public consultative process. The petitioners also sought of the Court to overturn its position in the earlier case of Law Association of Zambia and Chapter One Foundation Limited v. Attorney General 2019/CCZ/0013/0014 in which the petitioners sought the intervention of the Constitutional Court to halt the Constitution of Zambia (Amendment) Bill No 10 of 2019 (Bill 10).

 

The case is significant as it is the first time the Zambian Judiciary is stepping into the constitution amendment process and asserting that it has the power to enforce constitutional norms in the process. This is, therefore, an extremely significant legal development. On the other hand, the judgment lacks analytical precision, fails to draw a distinction between constituent and constituted power, and inadvertently drastically lowers the threshold for crafting a legitimate constitution. I start by highlighting the positive aspects of the judgment, before I return to indicate what I consider its weaknesses.

First, the judges showed remarkable courage to take a position clearly not aligned with that of the executive in the constitution amendment process in order to protect the current constitution from being amended for short-term political goals. This contrasts sharply with the entrenched past timidity and indifference of courts on the issue of constitution amendment or constitution making. The judiciary was, on several occasions, in the cases of Nkumbula v. Attorney General (1972) ZR 111 (HC); Nkumbula v. Attorney General (1972) ZR 204 (CA); Derrick Chitala (Suing as Secretary General of ZDC) v. Attorney General (1995-1997) ZR 91; and Law Association of Zambia and Chapter One Foundation Limited v. Attorney General 2019/CCZ/0013/14, asked to intervene to foster constitutionalism in the constitution-making process and safeguard the constitution. Yet in all these cases, the courts choose to stay aloof and leave the constitution at the mercy of partisan interests. From this perspective, the judiciary has always been interwoven with other branches of government in arresting the growth of constitutionalism. It has often been part of the problem and a willing participant in undermining democratic constitution-building, and not a guardian of the constitution. As a result, the Zambian judiciary has been an apt fit of Odinkalu’s observation that “the first generation of constitutions and bills of rights in common law Africa was destroyed not much by the intolerance of the executive as by the enthusiastic abdication of judicial responsibilities by the judges.” By overturning this history of indifference, the judges, to paraphrase Fombad, proved that they are no longer timorous souls but boisterous, bold spirits committed to the growth of constitutionalism. In a book published in 2020, Supreme Court judge (now Chief Justice), Mumba Malila, lamented about jurisprudence expressed in cases such as the Nkumbula ones and expressed hope that “in present times similar cases would be decided with completely different considerations in mind.” That hope has been given life in the Munir Zulu case.

 

Second, the Court’s combined interpretation of Articles 2 and 128 (3)(c) to the effect that it has jurisdiction to superintend the constitutionality of the conduct of the executive the pre-Bill stage is generally supportive, but only to the extent that it is applying constitutional norms while respecting separation of powers. Putting aside the issue of the amendment power of the legislature for a while (which is discussed further below), it appears that the petitioners did not argue that Parliament had no power to amend the Constitution. Rather, the contention was that the manner the pre-Bill reforms were carried out was in violation of several express and implied constitutional values and principles that bind both the executive and the legislature. Focusing only on this narrow point, the position of the Court is correct that it is clothed with the power to enforce constitutional norms even at this stage. The position, however, should be nuanced. This is because when the Constitution imposes obligations on organs of the state and the concerned organs do not perform their role in line with the stated obligations, the Courts have a duty to intervene to enforce the constitutional obligations. All constitutional power must be accountable under the constitution. The South African Constitutional Court, for example, in the case of Doctors for Life International v. The Speaker of the National Assembly and Others, for example, held that once a question is raised about the manner in which the legislature exercises its power, that triggers the Court’s interpretive role as it is vested with power to interpret the Constitution. The interpretive approach taken by the Constitutional Court under Article 128, therefore, appears correct.

The case of Doctors for Life International v. The Speaker of the National Assembly and Others is also instructive on how the Constitutional Court could have developed the jurisprudence further in view of the doctrine of separation of powers in order to set a threshold for ripeness of matters for adjudication before it. In this matter, the Court had to determine if it had the power to nullify a Bill which had not yet become law and also, assuming the Court had no such power, if it could provide declaratory relief where the legislature disregarded constitutional obligations in drafting a Bill, although not yet law.  With regard to the first issue, the Court held that it is more appropriate to review an Act of Parliament and not a Bill in order to respect the principle of separation of powers and to avoid prescribing to Parliament how it should perform its role. However, with regard to how Parliament exercised that power in the legislative process, the Court took the view that the Constitution binds all entities and organs of the state. Therefore, if the legislature or executive, in the legislative process, violated constitutional norms, the Court could intervene to enforce constitutional obligations. The Court categorically held:

“But under our constitutional democracy, the Constitution is the supreme law.  It is binding on all branches of government, and no less on Parliament.  When it exercises its legislative authority, Parliament must act in accordance with, and within the limits of, the Constitution, and the supremacy of the Constitution requires that the obligations imposed by it must be fulfilled.  Courts are required by the Constitution to ensure that all branches of government act within the law and fulfil their constitutional obligations.  This Court has been given the responsibility of being the ultimate guardian of the Constitution and its values.”

However, in the Zambian context, there are provisions of the Constitution that suggest that the Court can intervene with the legislative process if what is intended could lead to the violation of basic norms of the Constitution. Article 2 of the Constitution, for example, empowers every citizen to prevent violations of the Constitution. It states: ‘Every person has the right and duty to— (a) defend this Constitution; and (b) resist or prevent a person from overthrowing, suspending or illegally abrogating this Constitution.’ The use of the word “prevent” under Article 2(b) suggests that one does not have to wait until the action is completed (in this case, the enactment of a Bill into law). From this perspective, the court made the right decision that it has the power to adjudicate the pre-Bill process. But considering the significance of the doctrine of separation of powers, the Court should have gone further to develop the jurisprudence to indicate the threshold that removes matters from within the internal realm of each arm of government to warrant its interference in order to enforce constitutional norms.

Despite the laudability of the Constitutional Court judgment, it also has inherent weaknesses that negate its importance.

First, the Constitutional Court either decided to deliberately distort history or acted out of gross ignorance of the constitutional history of the country when it asserted that all past constitutional amendments were framed through a public participatory process (led by either a commission of inquiry or a technical committee). Here is what the Constitutional Court stated in its own words: 

“A structured and wide consultative process at inception is evident in the unique constitutional history and development of this country.  We take judicial notice that past attempted or successful constitutional amendment processes have been conducted by independent/expert bodies and that their output consisted of public documentation of the consultation process, such as a green paper or constitutional review commission report complete with intended draft provisions.”

It is based on this view that the Court concluded that the current amendment process was inconsistent with established national practice and hence unconstitutional.

However, the position asserted by the Court in the above quotation is factually incorrect, and it appears that the Court, despite having a dedicated pool of research advocates, succumbed to unresearched popular views about the country only having had four or five constitutional amendments. This is at variance with the truth, as there have been several more constitutional amendments, and most of them did not include a public process beyond what is prescribed under Article 79 of the Constitution.

Examples of constitutional amendments that did not have a public consultative process beyond that stipulated in Article 79 are legion. These include the Constitution (Amendment) Act No. 5 of 1969 which abolished the Barotseland Agreement as it provided that the Barotseland Agreement shall “…cease to have effect, and all rights (whether vested or otherwise), liabilities and obligations thereupon shall lapse;” the Constitution (Amendment) Act No. 44 of 1970 which renamed Barotseland as Western Province (in fact in 1970 alone, there were three constitutional amendments, that is, Constitution (Amendment) Act  No. 44 of 1970, Constitution (Amendment) Act No 58 of 1970 and Constitution (Amendment) Act No. 12  of 1970) and Constitution of Zambia (Amendment) Act No. 20 of 2009 aligning the government financial year with the Gregorian calendar year. It might surprise the Court to even know that the initial change to the one-party rule was in 1972 (and not in 1973 as is popularly known) and was made by an amendment to the Constitution without a wider public process. The 1973 constitution, based on the Chona commission report, was fait accompli.

 

Second, the Court distinguished the current case from its decision in the Bill 10 judgment. As already noted above, the Court drew two bases for the distinction. First, that in the Bill 10 Judgment, the challenge revolved around the constitutionality of a Bill, that is, the Constitution of Zambia (Amendment) Bill No 10 of 2019. Second that the petitioners in that case challenged the constitutionality of the process leading to the tabling of Bill 10. According to the Constitutional Court, the Bill 10 judgment is acceptable because the constitution-making process then was chaperoned by an Act of Parliament, the National Dialogue Forum Act. The distinction was, therefore, that there was no guiding legislation and that the challenge raised related to the pre-Bill stage of framing the constitutional amendment. It dismissed the claim that its earlier case was per incuriam. This position is troubling on many fronts. First, the Court appears to have misread its Bill 10 judgment in order to make it sound that the case had not raised ‘process’ rights with regard to constitution making. Contrary to the assertion of the Court, the Bill 10 petition called on the Court to decide on the basis of the values and principles enshrined in the Constitution and not just the narrow issues of compliance with Article 79. In fact, there was no dispute about the competence of the legislature regarding Article 79.

Of more interest, however, is the fact that in the Bill 10 Judgment, the Constitutional Court dismissed the petition on the grounds that it lacked jurisdiction. The Court came to this conclusion on the basis of Article 128(3) of the Constitution, which states:

 “Subject to Article 28, a person who alleges that— (a) an Act of Parliament or statutory instrument; (b) an action, measure or decision taken under law; or (c) an act, omission, measure or decision by a person or an authority; contravenes this Constitution, may petition the Constitutional Court for redress.” 

The Constitutional Court, based on this provision, held that it is only clothed with jurisdiction to review Acts of Parliament and not Bills, as the provision does not expressly mention Bills. The Court felt buttressed by the drafting history of the Constitution, whereby the express provision clothing the court with jurisdiction to review Bills was deleted in the draft Constitution and never made it into law.

By not facing its earlier decision head-on, the Constitutional Court created the anomalous situation where it considers that it has jurisdiction to interrogate pre-Bill conduct, but once that conduct manifests itself in a Bill, its jurisdiction mysteriously vanishes. In the circumstances, without the Court reversing itself from the Bill 10 judgment, it would anomalously entail that the Court has no jurisdiction to question Bill 7. It is a disingenuous position and a jurisprudential anomaly that the Court needs to correct in future decisions.

 

The third problem with the position taken by the Constitutional Court is that, by making past constitutional review commissions the measuring rod of what is acceptable, the Court unknowingly significantly lowered the threshold for consensus-driven and ‘independent’ constitution-making.

Part of the problem why the country’s constitutional order has not yet been settled because all past constitution-making processes have been executive-driven, using the model of constitution review commissions. As Professor Melvin Mbao correctly observed, 

In the case of Zambia, previous constitutional projects have been dominated by the executive.  Successive governments have used the Inquiries Act to appoint Constitutional Review Commissions.  The terms of reference were determined by the President, reserving to the government the power to accept and reject any or all recommendations, etc, made by the Commission.”

Therefore, contrary to the views of the Constitutional Court, constitution review commissions have been part and parcel of the problem and not the solution. The deeply troubling one-party constitution of 1973 was accomplished via this mechanism. The threshold set by the Constitutional Court has no normative threshold or content. The President only needs to set up a commission or technical committee to consult the people and, therefore, meets the constitutional requirements for the pre-Bill process. Once this is done, the ensuing content does not seem to matter, or at least the Court set no standard by which to judge the content.

The final issue demonstrates the lack of analytical precision by the Court as it failed to draw a distinction between the concepts of constituent and constituted power. The Court asserted that constituent power resides in the people and that the people as a constituent power are the direct source of the constitution, and therefore, it is only the people that can frame constitutional amendments through an exercise of their sovereign power. Hence, the need to always have a wide consultative process whenever amending the constitution. Because of this, the Court thought that Article 79, the amendment clause in the Constitution, was merely formalistic. To fulfil its view, the Court held that “The only way to properly protect the constitution is to take every amendment process through a wide consultative process with the people, at inception.”

This is incorrect and not supported by constitutional practice or theory anywhere else. As already noted above, there have already been several constitutional amendments in the history of the country that never had a wide public process. The confusion in the judgment arises from the failure to distinguish between constituent and constituted power and the assigned or proper role of each in constitutional design. Constituent power is the power to establish the constitutional order of a nation. It is original and unmediated, at least in terms of logical grounding.  As Professor Yaniv Roznai has observed, constituent power is original power that is “exercised in a legal vacuum, whether in the establishment of the first constitution of a new State or the repeal of the existing constitutional order, for instance, with regime change. It acts outside the forms, procedures, and limits established by the constitution.” Once the constitution is established, constituent power retreats and becomes dormant as its task is established, and all public power is henceforth exercised under the constitution. On the other hand, the power exercised under the constitution is constituted power and includes the power to amend the constitution. Constituted power is legal power derived from or delegated under the constitution. Based on this distinction, only an exercise of constituent power should result in a change of the constitution or a substantial part of it. All reforms or alterations that go to the substance of the constitution should be reserved to the people as the constituent power. However, amendment power is delegated and is properly exercised by those upon whom it is conferred without any need to invoke or stir constituent power. The exercise of constituted power (amendment power), however, is not intended to change the substance of the constitution but merely the text. As Prof Richard Albert notes, “The procedures of constitutional amendment give lawmakers and the people a way to rid their constitution of an observed fault or to update it without having to write an altogether new constitution.”

The power of amendment is, therefore, preservative and not destructive of the Constitution. It is intended to maintain its existence while adjusting it to the needs of the time without changing its core or substance. Prof Roznai aptly summarises the nature of this power: “The amendment process is designed for the textual change of constitutional provisions, but not of fundamental political decisions that form the substance of the constitution: The authority to amend the constitution … means that other constitutional provisions can substitute for individual or multiple ones. They may do so, however, only under the presupposition that the identity and continuity of the constitution as an entirety is preserved … The authority for constitutional amendment contains only the grant of authority to undertake changes, additions, extensions, deletions, etc., in constitutional provisions that preserve the constitution itself. It is not the authority to change the particular basis of this jurisdiction for constitutional revisions.”

Once this distinction is drawn and understood, it becomes clear that Article 79 of the constitution clothes the legislature with constituted and not constituent power. It is, therefore, incorrect to assert, as did the Constitutional Court, that Article 79 is a mere formalistic clog in the exercise of constituent power. The test should rather have been whether the proposed changes went to the substance or core of the constitution, which would trigger constituent power, or if the proposed changes were simply ironing creases, which would have been within the full competence of the legislature to accomplish under Article 79. That is the approach some countries that have adopted the basic structure doctrine have taken. For example, in the case of Njoya v.  Attorney General (2005), the Kenyan High Court rejected the claim that the amendment power under the Constitution includes the power to make those changes that amount to the replacement of the Constitution. It indicated that the amendment “plainly means that Parliament may amend, repeal and replace as many provisions as desired provided the document retains its character as the existing Constitution,” and that “alteration of the Constitution does not involve the substitution thereof with a new one or the destruction of the identity or existence of the Constitution altered.” It should, however, be noted that the Kenyan Supreme Court in the case of Attorney General and Others v. David Ndii and Others Petition No 12 of 2021 rejected the application of the basic structure doctrine to Kenya as the 2010 Kenyan constitution had enshrined sufficient safeguards from the arbitrary constitutional changes.

It follows then that the holding of the Court that every intended amendment requires resort to constituent power is grossly mistaken and a failure to distinguish two interrelated concepts of constituent and constituted power in constitutional law. 




ABOUT THE AUTHOR

Dr. O’Brien Kaaba is a lecturer in law at the University of Zambia and a senior research fellow at the Southern African Institute for Policy and Research (SAIPAR).





The views and opinions presented in this article or multimedia content are solely those of the author(s) and may not represent the opinions or stance of Amulufeblog.com.

Post a Comment